Michel Revel, M.D., Ph.D.
Department of Molecular Genetics, Weizmann Institute of Science, Rehovot Member of the UNESCO International Committee on Bioethics

Evaluating any new technology and its ethical implications, especially when there are human applications, first requires clear definitions and a good understanding of the subject. Words like "human cloning" can be frightening, and if they are not correctly understood in their technical context it can become impossible to deal with their import in a reasonable way. Therefore, it is better to begin with a review of the technical aspects of cloning as well as an evaluation of the feasibility of potential applications so that the discussion will be, as far as possible, a reasoned one.

I. TECHNICAL REVIEW: CLONING MAMMALS
Is it feasible to reproduce humans by cloning? In the simplest terms, this would be one more method of assisted reproduction to be added to those which are already available, such as in-vitro fertilization of ova with sperm or intracytoplasmic sperm injection (ICSI).

Cloning, which has been the subject of experimentation on cattle and sheep for the last ten years, is in fact the "fertilization" of an enucleated oocyte with genetic material from the nucleus of a diploid cell taken from either an embryonic or an adult donor, the latter having been achieved for the first time in Ian Wilmut's recent experiment.1

Cloning by such "nuclear transfer" is accomplished in several steps:

  1. obtaining an oocyte by the now classic methods of injecting gonadotropin hormones;
  2. enucleation of the oocyte by inserting a fine pipette in order to draw out the non-condensed chromatin which is located under the polar body;
  3. inserting (with another pipette) a diploid cell from the donor to be cloned under the oocyte's zona pellucida;
  4. fusion of that cell to the enucleated oocyte by means of an electric pulse, which has the advantage of simultaneously activating the oocyte (a phenomenon normally triggered by contact with sperm);
  5. culturing of the "fertilized" oocyte to allow the initial stages of cell division leading to the development of a blastocyst;
  6. implantation in a surrogate mother who has undergone hormone treatment to prepare her to receive the blastocyst;
  7.  pregnancy to term and birth of the cloned fetus.

This procedure, developed in 1985 for cows and sheep in several veterinary laboratories such as those of Neal First at the University of Wisconsin at Madison, is the same as the procedure used by Wilmut's group to produce Dolly the Lamb. The significance of this group's experiment lies in the demonstration that the nucleus of a differentiated cell derived from an adult tissue is capable of directing embryonic development.

A survey of this type of animal cloning experimentation will enable us to understand the impact of the recent accomplishments. Until recently it was believed that only nuclear transfer from very early embryonic cells could be used for cloning. Therefore, until now only cells isolated from the blastocyst stage of embryonic development were used. Even at this stage, which occurs immediately after the first cellular divisions, only the undifferentiated embryonic stem (ES) cells derived from the inner cell mass were thought to be pluripotent and thus capable of contributing all three germinal layers of the embryo which are necessary for successful development. This is because cells derived from the surface of the blastula have already advanced too far in their ectodermic differentiation and therefore, it was believed, they could no longer revert to full developmental capacity. However, with sheep there seems to be greater flexibility, and embryonic cells which had undergone even more advanced differentiation (embryonic fibroblasts) could be successfully used for nuclear transfer.

The importance of the latest advance is to establish that fertilization can be accomplished by using an adult tissue cell derived from the mammary gland of a sheep. But the technical problems in this procedure remain great, as can be seen in the following chart which summarizes cloning attempts in sheep.

This table shows the preliminary nature of research in the field and points out the technical difficulties in applying the procedure in humans. The success rate in obtaining blastocysts and in achieving implantation is low, and the number of viable animals at term is even lower. The number of human oocytes that would be required is at present much too high. There are also many other obstacles to be overcome. Genetic analysis of the clones shows that they are frequently polyploid, indicating certain aberrations in cellular division leading to an unequal complement of chromosomes in the daughter cells. In addition, the embryos are often mosaic, i.e., they exhibit polyploid cells only in certain tissues. Since polyploidy is a characteristic of cancerous cells, the fate of these tissues over the course of years remains uncertain. This is a technical problem which certainly must be overcome.

Another problem is the activation of the oocyte in order to initiate cellular division. Certain proteins in the sperm normally initiate this activation, and these proteins are of course missing when nuclear transfer from a donor cell is used for fertilization. The electric pulse which is used to initiate cellular division seems to solve the problem only partially but there might be differences here among various species. Another important difference is the condition of the chromatin: it seems that in quiescent sheep cells, produced by causing the cells to exit the growth cycle and arrest in G0, the chromatin is less modified (e.g., by methylation of the DNA) than in other species. In addition, the sheep oocyte itself may be more capable of reversing these modifications, thus explaining why Dolly could be obtained from the nucleus of an adult cell and why the use of embryonic fibroblasts resulted in at least four live lambs. With monkeys two births were obtained, but only with nuclei from pre-blastular cells.

Extrapolating these data to man is not easy. Perhaps the procedure will be easy; or perhaps it will be even more difficult to clone humans. In this regard, it is interesting to note that ICSI had been considered a very difficult procedure with animals, although it succeeds well in humans2.

Donor cell type Embryos obtained

Embryos transferred
to mother

Pregnancies Births % Births/transfer
Embryonic stem cells

385

98

15

4

4

Fetal fibroblasts

172

40

5

3

8

Mammary epithelium

277

29

1-2

1-2*

3 *

* a single living animal

There is another question which must be considered in evaluating the success of cloning: to what extent are the clones genetically identical? The principles of cloning ought to guarantee that the DNA sequences of the clone are identical to those of the donor of the nucleus. Animal experimentation has not yet demonstrated that this is true. Studies of genetic markers in cows have in fact shown that there could be unforeseen rearrangements. DNA sequencing techniques are still too slow and limited to allow checking whole genomes of cloned and donor animals. Epigenetic alterations in the chromatin of various chromosomes leading to alterations in the expression of gene activity cannot yet be fully detected.

Further, the oocyte contributes mitochondrial DNA, whose influence on the whole of the organism, beyond the development of the mitochondria, is still unknown. Every human being has maternal mitochondrial DNA, whereas half of his nuclear genome is contributed by the father. In cloning humans it is unknown what will happen to the at least thirty so-called "imprinted" genes whose expression depends on their paternal or maternal origin.

Taking all these problems and unknowns into consideration, First has calculated that phenotypical identity in a cloned cow could be as low as 70% with respect to the donor of the nucleus. Since one of the main reasons to clone is to preserve the identity of genetic characteristics, for example the milk production in cows, variations of 30% are surely unacceptable among clones! Even patches of colored hair on cloned animals are not identical because hair coloring does not depend solely on the genome, but is influenced by certain events in the course of embryonic tissue development. The persistence of some maternal nuclear DNA in the enucleated oocyte cannot be entirely eliminated. The influence of the surrogate mother and placental location are also variable factors. Another major cause of variation is nutrition, which is not identical even in animal twins raised in the same environmental conditions. The influence of the environment, including education, would be immeasurably more important in humans.

II. THE BENEFITS OF CLONING IN ANIMALS
Genetic improvement by crossbreeding animals (hybridization) has always been viewed as an acceptable technique for developing characteristics of benefit to man. Among domestic animals, cows and sheep are the principle sources of milk for human consumption. Genetic crossbreeding has led to an increase in milk production, but the resultant hybrids are not always stable and consistent. One of the principal applications of cloning would be a greater stability in the preservation of desired characteristics even though absolute consistency might be impossible, as indicated above. A similar application of cloning would pertain to the quality of meat raised for human consumption.

Genetic research has in recent years led to the use of animals in the production of pharmaceutical products. Targeting a gene for expression in the mammary gland leads to secretion of large quantities of certain desirable proteins in the animal's milk. Production rates are extremely high and can reach several dozen grams per liter, as in the case of human albumin used for transfusion, coagulation factors used in the treatment hemophilia, and other therapeutic proteins.

These transgenic animals can be maintained by sexual reproduction through mating of transgenic males and females. Nevertheless, it is impossible to guarantee perfect genetic identity for the rest of the genome, and this can be an obstacle to commercial exploitation. In fact, one of the prerequisites for obtaining authorization for new pharmaceutical products is absolute consistency in production. If a pharmaceutical product is produced by a living animal, it might be impossible to guarantee such consistency and authorization for commercial production might be required for each animal involved in production. If the animal accidentally dies, the commercial investment (clinical trial on the product) would be lost and would have to be repeated with another animal.

Cloning could in theory solve this problem. A herd of cloned animals might be considered sufficiently identical to be covered by a single authorization for drug registration. The example of Dolly demonstrates that a nucleus from a mammary gland cell possessing desirable genetic characteristics can be transferred to produce a clone.

More generally, cloning may be useful in the generation of transgenic animals. This is accomplished today by genetic manipulation of pluripotent embryonic stem cells (ES), which still have the capacity to differentiate into various specialized types of tissue elements. Introducing the genetically modified ES cells into blastocytes, one first obtains mosaic animals, from which are then selected those which have the desired gene in their gametes and can therefore transmit it to their off-spring. By crossbreeding, one can finally produce homozygous progeny.

This procedure could be simplified and shortened by transferring the nucleus of a genetically manipulated cell directly into an enucleated oocyte leading to the birth of a transgenic animal in a single step. Further, it would be unnecessary to work with embryonic stem cells, which are not the easiest to manipulate genetically. Instead the nucleus of various somatic cells, e.g., fibroblasts, could be used to lead to the birth of transgenic animals.

This is not the place to consider whether man has a right to engage in genetic manipulation of animals. Such manipulations have a very long history, having been practiced with various techniques in different historical periods. Inasmuch as the procedure does not involve additional cruelty vis-a-vis the animal, cloning should be justified under these rights.

III. THE POSSIBLE AIMS OF CLONING IN HUMANS
None of the considerations favoring cloning in animals, as discussed above, is applicable to the cloning of humans. Transgenic acquisition of genetic characteristics affecting human gametes is universally considered to be prohibited (or subject to a moratorium) even for therapeutic purposes. Reproduction by cloning is a way of genetically manipulating gametes (i.e., by injecting genetic material from a donor into an oocyte). Nonetheless, it is proper to ask under what conditions this technology could be accepted for therapeutic purposes and to see whether applications do or do not transgress the prohibition against genetic manipulation of human gametes.

1) Applications in Transplantation
One of the most interesting scenarios proposed by J. A. Thomson of the Wisconsin Regional Primate Research Center is the application of cloning to produce transplantable tissues without actually producing any cloned humans. Such tissues would be syngeneic with respect to the donor and therefore completely compatible with him. They could be obtained by in-vitro culturing of pluripotent embryonic cells.

The steps in such a therapeutic procedure would be as follows:

This differentiation takes place under conditions allowing the isolation of different types of tissue so that pancreatic beta cells can be recovered and implanted into the patient. These cells will be syngeneic with the recipient, thus eliminating the problem of rejection.

This scenario could be applied to other tissues and could also be used for genetic modification. For example, brain cells modified by the genes responsible for the production of dihydroxyphenylalanine (L-Dopa) and dopamine could be obtained for transplantation into the brains of Parkinson's patients. Perhaps neuron grafts could be developed for nerve or brain regeneration. Use of cytokines and other specific factors could produce various tissues such as blood vessels. Such tissues would be immunologically identical with the individual from whom the "fertilizing" nucleus was transferred.

Ethical Aspects
The question here is the ethics of the embryo status. There are regulations governing the medical use of embryonic cells derived from spontaneous or therapeutic abortions. In the present case, we will be culturing embryos for the purpose of producing graftable tissues prior to implantation of the embryo. The question revolves around the morality of using human embryos in their initial stages of development.

In certain cultures and religions, and particularly Christianity, the fertilized human oocyte is thought of as possessing a soul, thus acquiring all the rights of a human being. According to this view there is no difference between killing an embryo prior to implantation and murdering a newborn infant to utilize its organs.

Other cultures and religions do not consider the early embryo to have all the rights of a human being. Judaism, and also Islam, do not confer human status on an embryo before forty days of gestation have elapsed. According to this view, the above technique of producing graftable tissue would be acceptable. Ethical guidelines accepted by the scientific community permit maintaining cultured embryos for around two weeks, that is, before they form their first nerve cells.

The complexity of the ethical issues involved here is clear and comparable with attitudes towards unneeded, frozen embryos which have been stored during assisted reproduction (IVF). Once pregnancy has been established, what should be done with the extra embryos? The recent controversy in the United Kingdom over the fate of frozen embryos after the five-year waiting period imposed by law demonstrates the diversity of opinions.

Another example would be preimplantation diagnostic testing which involves taking away about half of the embryo (at the stage of 2-3 cells) and ruining it in order to determine the presence or absence of a genetic disease so as to decide whether to implant and give birth to the other half. Here, too, a number of countries permit the technique for therapeutic purposes but other countries prohibit it. It must be noted that the possibility of preserving frozen half-embryos in order to produce tissues for transplantation, should the person born from the other half of the embryo (the twin) need such intervention in the course of his life, has been mentioned since the inception of in-vitro fertilization research by Dr. R. Edwards. Cloning would be more ethical from this point of view since it would be done only as needed in real medical situations rather than in anticipation of possible future needs.

The application of cloning that we consider here would not violate the prohibition against manipulating germ cells because there would be no changes in future generations. If the use of an embryo for such purposes is not to be considered an act of murder, the technique could perhaps be acceptable as a method of producing tissues for grafts and transplants.

Despite the attractiveness of this technique, we should not underestimate the dangers of neoplastic transformations or other mutations which could result in the course of culturing embryonic tissue. The advantages and dangers inherent in the technique must be carefully studied before applying it to man. Thomson's research on primates will possibly provide the necessary assurances.

2) Use in Assisted Reproduction
 In the accepted framework of treatment for infertile couples, a germ cell is often obtained from a third-party donor. An infertile couple might prefer a child with a genetic composition identical to one of theirs rather than a child whose genes come from a stranger. Use of a nucleus taken from the husband or wife would permit the gynecologist to offer such an option.

In fertile couples where one of the spouses has a severe genetic disorder, cloning the other spouse could be considered for similar reasons.

Ethical Aspects
 The technique would respect the concern against adultery which poses a serious problem in using sperm donated by anyone besides the husband. The fear of adultery is augmented by the possibility of incest which could result from the union of the person born of donated sperm or oocyte with a half-brother of half-sister born of the same donor. Further, a post-menopausal woman has the possibility of becoming a surrogate mother for her husband's child, the oocyte being donated by another woman. In certain religions, this would also be considered adulterous. In principle, therefore, cloning might be licit in such cases and even preferable.

The objection that this implies manipulating germ cells should prevent its application. However, in this case there is no insertion or deletion of a gene as in therapeutic manipulation of germ cells. It could be argued that the genetic patrimony transmitted to the offspring is unaltered, even having been "tested" in the life of the donor. The question, therefore, is whether a genome derived from a mature, adult cell is really capable of accurately reproducing embryonic development in man and whether mutations might not occur in such a genome. The dangers of polyploidy mentioned in connection with animals require great caution when applying the technique in man.

3) Potential Nontherapeutic Uses
a) Homosexual Reproduction
Experience has shown that assisted reproduction is often preferred by lesbian couples. Instead of using donated sperm, cloning one of the partners could be considered. In addition, cloning would for the first time permit genetic reproduction of male homosexuals, although a woman would still be needed to donate an oocyte and carry the pregnancy. Of course, such a woman would not be the genetic mother of the offspring, who would be the "twin" of one of the males.

Ethical Aspects
The ethical aspects in this case will depend on society's approach to the individual rights of homosexuals. A priori, the right to choose one's partner is analogous to the right to refuse adulterous fertilization. Nonetheless, the therapeutic aspect is less clear in this case than in the case of heterosexual couples where fertility is normal and medical intervention merely restores the natural state. A homosexual couple must realize that reproduction is impossible and that their infertility can hardly be considered pathological.

Further, the same considerations which occur in assisted reproduction, discussed above, can be applied in this case.

b) Replacing a Deceased Child
A couple having just lost a child might want a replacement as similar as possible to the deceased. A biopsy of the deceased could be used for cloning. A physical double would be obtained although it would not necessarily be identical and certainly would not reproduce the personality of the deceased.

Ethical Aspects
Although their motives are understandable, this is a relatively arbitrary choice; in no sense is it a therapeutic procedure. One of the major concerns in preimplantation procedures is exactly the problem of preventing arbitrary decisions. Take, for example, sex selection. Although we could agree to a couple at high risk for hemophilia or Huntington's chorea choosing a female embryo in order to prevent bringing a sick boy into the world, personal convenience alone cannot justify the predetermination of an embryo's sex. This is why sex selection is prohibited in a number of countries.

Cloning in order to produce a duplicate offspring to replace a deceased child would be a flagrant example of choice motivated by convenience. In addition, culturing the deceased child's cells may be an offense to the dignity of the deceased since it is not being done to save another person's life as is the case in post-mortem organ transplantation. Finally, such a practice would tend to create the impression that cloning transfers psychological and behavioral characteristics although, as studies of identical twins have shown, it is by no means clear to what extent these are genetically controlled. Figures would show that cognitive aptitudes are only about half genetically controlled2. Would not physical similarity be unbearable if the cloned child does not have the desired mental characteristics?

4) Eugenic Manipulation of Gametes
As with cloning of cows and sheep, some people consider human cloning to be a technology which will allow the reproduction of desirable genetic characteristics. The least shocking application of this idea would be the duplication of genetic characteristics of resistance to certain diseases since it is clear that inherited genes play a role in predisposition to cardiovascular disease and cancers. Considering the beneficial role of those genes responsible for suppressing tumors, duplication of a "better" genome could produce groups of human clones with genetic resistance to cancer.

Duplicating certain physical characteristics, like sex or size, could be desirable in producing groups of people particularly suited to certain activities (large people for certain sports or as soldiers, small people as astronauts, etc.). The ultimate aberration would be the duplication of individuals for their psychological or intellectual characteristics, assuming that genetics determines these characteristics more than education and environment.

Ethical Aspects
 In this case there is no difference between cloning and the genetic manipulation of germ cells, which is prohibited today by every national and international ethical convention. Furthermore, the eugenic perspective is evident in this case, and it is particularly condemnable because it is not intended to correct any genetic default of an individual, but to create a collectivity in which an arbitrary standard is enforced. The argument that it is better "to avoid the genetic roulette" inherent in sexual reproduction makes clear the anti-natural character of the procedure. Richard Dawkins has pointed out how much nature seems to favor genetic diversity resulting from sexual reproduction - for example, in the crosspollination of flowers which frequently requires complicated ecosystems of pollinating insects - while nature seems to avoid inbreeding by self-fertilization in the plant kingdom and hermaphroditism in animals, although we do not yet really understand the reasons for this. Anthropology has shown that complicated rules have guaranteed exogamy since the origin of human society. Asexual reproduction would run counter to the prevalent mode of nature. Before acquiring total knowledge of all human genes with an understanding of their functions and multiple interactions, any genetic manipulation is even more a game of roulette with unpredictable results. Biology teaches us that genetic diversity is central to evolution and that hybrid vigor is the rule. Any technique of reproduction based on the duplication of gene sequences instead of the randomness of chromosome selection in sexual reproduction could very well eliminate the mechanisms by which genetic errors are corrected. If so, cloning could do more genetic damage than good.

IV. HUMAN CLONING: ENVISIONING AN ETHICAL APPROACH
In dealing with technological advances, ethics has the task of defining the limits of what is acceptable. A complete prohibition would be counterproductive. Proof that it is possible to use the genetic material of a mature, differentiated cell for programming the development of an embryo, as was recently demonstrated with sheep, poses a new ethical challenge. Having examined the perspectives that this advance might have for human beings, we can draw several conclusions regarding the feasibility, desirability, and morality of such applications.

1) Is Human Cloning Feasible?
The technical problems have not yet been solved. The success rate in animal cloning is still so low that it would seem premature to attempt cloning humans. Particularly disquieting is the fact that embryonic development pursuant to cloning could be abnormal, exhibiting polyploidy and mosaics. In addition, genetic and phenotypic identity between the cloned organism and the donor of the genome, which is the whole purpose of the technique, has not yet been proven. We cannot ignore the contribution of maternal mitochondrial DNA, nor the influence of the oocyte's cytoplasm on embryonic development. Since every clone requires an enucleated oocyte, these influences will be variable. We cannot entirely eliminate maternal influence on genetic programming during pregnancy. More scientific research is required before thinking about safely applying the procedure to humans. This is why research must be allowed to proceed.

2) Is Human Cloning Desirable?
The technique should only be used for therapeutic purposes. As we have seen, there are two very different potential uses of therapeutic cloning. The first is for producing syngeneic grafts which can only be made on a culture of cells derived from an embryo prior to implantation. Such a procedure should be governed by the rules of therapeutic use of human embryos.

The second is actual procreation as a means of treating sterility or guaranteeing the absence of homozygous genetic disorders in couples at risk. In these cases, the technique of assisted reproduction by cloning would be of interest in overcoming the religious objections to extramarital gamete donation.

The implementation of the technique would therefore have to respond to individual need without being arbitrary or based on mere convenience. This would eliminate non-therapeutic procedures. The dignity of the person or couple under care as well as that of the offspring would have to be respected. Before implementing the technique, it would therefore be necessary to be certain that the potential cloned offspring would be genetically and phenotypically healthy. Much further research is needed on primates to provide such safeguards.

Cloning groups of humans in order to obtain socially desirable genetic characteristics should be completely prohibited. Not only is this a violation of the individual's liberty and dignity, it is also a violation of the surrogate mother's rights. Reproduction by cloning implies that every clone has a biological mother who bore the child. This also makes unthinkable production of children by "industrial" cloning and should dissipate the fears of "baby factories."

3) Is Human Cloning Immoral?
Being fundamentally different from natural, sexual procreation, cloning without doubt represents a new way by which mankind could control its own nature.

Is cloning unnatural? Reproduction by parthenogenesis and propagation by cuttings is well known in the vegetable kingdom, microorganisms, plants, and insects. Rabbi Menachem ha-Meiri, a fourteenth-century commentator on the Talmud, relates (on Sanhedrin 67b) that reproduction without sex is part of nature. Cloning is therefore not a human innovation, rather it exists in nature and has been performed in the laboratory since the first half of this century. Jean Rostand has expressed enthusiasm about his experiments with sea urchins and frogs and since 1956 has been predicting "solitary reproduction in man."5

Asexual reproduction in man poses a provocative moral question. Can we imagine a world where instead of having fathers and mothers children will have older twin brothers or mothers who are also their older twin sisters? Can we imagine a world populated only by women, men having lost their biological raison d'etre? Surely the response is not evident.

If cloning remains strictly limited to individual therapeutic applications, society could, without abandoning its values, accept it as another modality of procreation. If, on the other hand, asexual reproduction by cloning becomes a fad, or even worse, an imposed norm for eugenic purposes, dehumanization will surely result. Sexuality is a cultural value in itself. But it is also a biological value, if we are to judge by the success of those species which reproduce sexually. Evolution depends on the genetic mixing which occurs during sexual reproduction. Such mixing is probably also necessary to maintain the evolved state of a species. Cumulative errors in a genome which would perpetuate itself for several generations would in all probability be disastrous. We cannot even determine whether the genome of an adult cell carries errors or physical alterations in its DNA which will come to light in the course of the clone's life.

The multiplicity of individual human genomes is a source of richness for mankind, but we grasp only poorly the function of this diversity in the evident unity of mankind. The analogy of the diversity of cultures, where every culture constitutes a part of the anthropological definition of Homo sapiens, can perhaps help in understanding the idea of diversity within the unity of a species. Cloning of one or more human genomes would necessarily involve an arbitrary and restrictive choice which, if it becomes the social norm, would be dehumanizing. Aldous Huxley's Best of All Possible Worlds eloquently portrays the dangers of controlled reproduction of alphas, betas, and gammas. Religions express the responsibility and dignity of the individual because our species cannot exist unless the individual is respected. So it is with the human genome: no individual is genetically perfect or genetically deficient. We must consider the complexity and originality of each individual6 . Mass production by cloning of one or several human genomes would run counter to this fundamental genetic morality.

If viewed as a part of a social order, rather than as a therapeutic approach for individuals, cloning is immoral because it implies genetic determinism. As with any eugenic measure, cloning neglects the impact of education and the transmission of knowledge and traditions in the formation of the individual and society. Cloning creates the illusion that everything is genetically determined, which is a false, pseudoscientific premise as already seen in animal cloning since cloned animals do not exhibit phenotypic identity. A fortiori, studies of identical human twins have shown the influence of the environment which impacts almost as much as behavioral genetics on individual psychology. Groups of cloned children will not be uniform because they will necessarily have different biological mothers. Their education and feelings will not be identical. However, the mere physical resemblance, if widespread (whereas twins are exceptional), could be disturbing for society. This is why it would be reprehensible to promote in public the myth of cloning as a means of replicating copies of an "ideal" genome: this is an oversimplification which offends the intelligence of geneticists who are often the first to see the limits of genetic influence in man.

Nevertheless, it would be wrong to stop scientific research on this new method of reproduction. Several nations are already considering legislation to prohibit all research leading to human cloning. It is the responsibility of national and international ethics committees to define the modalities in which such research can be pursued in accord with the principles of medical ethics and the preservation of personal dignity. Depriving humanity of a penetrating knowledge of all potentialities of the living would be counterproductive. This argument was already evoked in the debate on germ-cell genetic manipulation. Assuming that scientific research will eventually lead to a safe method of eradicating certain genetic diseases, including certain cancers, would it not be licit to at least consider genetic manipulations, cloning, or any other method which would allow such "genetic surgery"? The Human Genome Project promises to provide complete knowledge regarding human genetics. But before such complete knowledge is acquired, it does not seem possible to evaluate the risks and benefits of germ line genetic manipulation. Based on these considerations, it seems wise to adopt a moratorium on germ line genetic manipulation in humans but not an a priori prohibition. The ethical debate must be continuously renewed for, as Rostand said in the name of Canon Tiberghien:7 "Moralists will possibly have to express their views on these questions. But, pity on the world if consulted they cannot agree." Genesis teaches the same lesson in the episode of the tower of Babel: in its commentary, the Zohar8 attributes the human failure to the incapability of the builders to understand each other's language and adds that only with united hearts and minds will mankind succeed in its endeavors. Scientists, politicians, religious leaders and philosophers must learn to speak the same language and understand each other. The ethical principles inherited from our religious tradition place man as a partner in God's creation, and from there derives man's responsibility in science and technology. Mastering human genetics is a great endeavor of our time. The ethical principles which must guide us are:

  1. Genetics should remain in the realm of medicine, aimed at therapy of suffering individuals.
  2. Genetic decisions should be made by individuals after proper counseling and should never be imposed by society.
  3. Individual needs being different, decisions should be made case by case, with respect for the dignity and rights of every member of the human family.

CONCLUSIONS
The ethical debate regarding reproduction by nuclear transfer (cloning), following the animal experiments and anticipating human applications, is just beginning. Technically speaking, research is still too preliminary to be of any safe and effective use in reproductive medicine. Nonetheless, a limited application in culturing syngeneic human tissues is conceivable with the aim of transplanting tissues or perhaps even organs. Extrapolating into the future when cloning might become one of several methods of assisted reproduction, the following ethical indications would seem to be sufficient:
  1. Cloning should be considered an example of germ line cell genetic manipulation and as such should fall under the current accepted moratorium. This moratorium is all the more necessary because the technique is still in its early stages of development.
  2. In the future, some exceptions may be authorized to permit cloning for specifically defined therapeutic purposes pursuant to freely given informed consent by the mother or by the couple which opts for cloning as a method of treating sterility or preventing serious genetic disease while, for example, eliminating the need of an extramarital gamete donor.
  3. Cloning should not be permitted for arbitrary, nontherapeutic purposes. It is essential that the dignity of the mother, of the genome donor and of the offspring be respected.
  4. Cloning must never become the social norm for reproduction. It must remain an individual procedure and never be applied to "produce" groups of humans with illusive, predetermined genetic characteristics.

COMMENTS
  1. Nature 385 (1997): 810-813.
  2. Govaerts, I., et al., Hum Reprod 11 (1996): 440-443.
  3. Bio Reprod 55 (1996): 254-259.
  4. Plomin, R., et al., Behavioral Genetics, Freeman and Co. (New York, 1997).
  5. Jean Rostand, Peut-on modifier l'homme? (Gallimard), p. 13.
  6. Leclerc et al., Intern J of Bioeth 4 (1993): 2889-92.
  7. Ibid., p. 99.
  8. Zohar, I, 76b.

back to assia